Results for 'David O. Renz'

955 found
Order:
  1. Organizations, ethics, and health care: Building an ethics infrastructure for a new era.David O. Renz & William B. Eddy - 1996 - Bioethics Forum 12 (2):29-39.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  2. Impartiality and Associative Duties: David O. Brink.David O. Brink - 2001 - Utilitas 13 (2):152-172.
    Consequentialism is often criticized for failing to accommodate impersonal constraints and personal options. A common consequentialist response is to acknowledge the anticonsequentialist intuitions but to argue either that the consequentialist can, after all, accommodate the allegedly recalcitrant intuitions or that, where accommodation is impossible, the recalcitrant intuition can be dismissed for want of an adequate philosophical rationale. Whereas these consequentialist responses have some plausibility, associational duties represent a somewhat different challenge to consequentialism, inasmuch as they embody neither impersonal constraints nor (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  3. Rational egoism and the separateness of persons.David O. Brink - 1997 - In Jonathan Dancy (ed.), Reading Parfit. Oxford, [England] ;: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 96--134.
  4. Perfectionism and the Common Good: Themes in the Philosophy of T. H. Green.David O. Brink - 2003 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 66 (2):390-390.
  5. Eudaimonism, Love and Friendship, and Political Community*: DAVID O. BRINK.David O. Brink - 1999 - Social Philosophy and Policy 16 (1):252-289.
    It is common to regard love, friendship, and other associational ties to others as an important part of a happy or flourishing life. This would be easy enough to understand if we focused on friendships based on pleasure, or associations, such as business partnerships, predicated on mutual advantage. For then we could understand in a straightforward way how these interpersonal relationships would be valuable for someone involved in such relationships just insofar as they caused her pleasure or causally promoted her (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  6.  33
    (2 other versions)The Status of Morality.David O. Brink & Thomas Carson - 1986 - Philosophical Review 95 (1):144.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  7. Legal Interpretation, Objectivity and Morality.David O. Brink - 2000 - In Brian Leiter (ed.), Objectivity in Law and Morals. New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 12--65.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  8. Mammalian chromodomain proteins: their role in genome organisation and expression.David O. Jones, Ian G. Cowell & Prim B. Singh - 2000 - Bioessays 22 (2):124-137.
    The chromodomain is a highly conserved sequence motif that has been identified in a variety of animal and plant species. In mammals, chromodomain proteins appear to be either structural components of large macromolecular chromatin complexes or proteins involved in remodelling chromatin structure. Recent work has suggested that apart from a role in regulating gene activity, chromodomain proteins may also play roles in genome organisation. This article reviews progress made in characterising mammalian chromodomain proteins and emphasises their emerging role in the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  9. Sidgwick's dualism of practical reason.David O. Brink - 1988 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 66 (3):291 – 307.
  10. Moral Realism: Facts and Norms. [REVIEW]David O. BRINK - 1991 - Ethics 101 (3):610-624.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   482 citations  
  11. „The Autonomy of Ethics “.David O. Brink - 2006 - In Michael Martin (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Atheism. Cambridge University Press. pp. 149--65.
  12. Prudence and Authenticity.David O. Brink - 2003 - Philosophical Review 112 (2):215-245.
    Prudence and authenticity are sometimes seen as rival virtues. Prudence,as traditionally conceived, is temporally neutral. It attaches no intrinsic significance to the temporal location of benefits or harms within the agent’s life; the prudent agent should be equally concerned about all parts of her life. But people’s values and ideals often change over time, sometimes in predictable ways, as when middle age and parenthood often temporize youthful radicalism or spontaneity with concerns for comfort,security, and predictability. In situations involving diachronic, intrapersonal (...)
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  13. (1 other version)The significance of desire.David O. Brink - 2008 - Oxford Studies in Metaethics 3:5-45.
  14. Leadership, Ethics and Responsibility to the Other.David Knights & Majella O’Leary - 2006 - Journal of Business Ethics 67 (2):125-137.
    Of recent time, there has been a proliferation of concerns with ethical leadership within corporate business not least because of the numerous scandals at Enron, Worldcom, Parmalat, and two major Irish banks – Allied Irish Bank (AIB) and National Irish Bank (NIB). These have not only threatened the position of many senior corporate managers but also the financial survival of some of the companies over which they preside. Some authors have attributed these scandals to the pre-eminence of a focus on (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   51 citations  
  15. (1 other version)Handout #2: Moral motivation and rationalism.David O. Brink - unknown
    We have looked at worries about expressivism and other forms of noncognitivism. The externalist solution may also seem to be a solution of last resort, because it may seem to deny the platitude that moral judgments are motivationally efficacious. For this reason, we might look seriously at rationalist theories of moral motivation, because they promise to represent moral judgments as intrinsically motivational without giving up cognitivism.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  5
    The opaqueness of God.David O. Woodyard - 1970 - Philadelphia,: Westminster Press.
  17. The Ethical Dimension of Personal Knowledge.David O. Jenkins - 1982 - Dissertation, Loyola University of Chicago
    My purpose in this dissertation is to show that a wide-ranging investigation of Michael Polanyi's epistemology and ontology taken together with his social-political writings reveals the possibility of explicating an ethical language which can be seen, in Polanyi's terms, to be tacit within these works. The work naturally divides into two parts: the first deals with Polanyi's epistemology and ontology; the second deals with the social and political writings. ;The first part consists in two major arguments: the epistemological and the (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  52
    Neo-pragmatism, communication, and the culture of creative democracy (review).David O. Kasdan - 2011 - Education and Culture 27 (1):69-72.
    Swartz, Campbell, and Pestana offer this original application of neo-pragmatism with the expressed desire to "rethink commonly accepted notions of community in order to imagine new possibilities for social, political, and economic organization—in short, new ways of imaging solidarity and citizenship with others, especially those who languish outside the range of our moral radar" (p. 2). Neither the rethinking of community nor the postulating of ideas for solidarity are unfamiliar concepts in the world of neo-pragmatism; perhaps those objectives are defining (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  71
    The Moral Asymmetry of Juvenile and Adult Offenders.David O. Brink - 2020 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 14 (2):223-239.
    Many commentators agree that the trend to try juveniles as adults fails to recognize that there should be an asymmetry in our treatment of juvenile and adult crime such that all else being equal juvenile crime deserves less punishment than does adult crime. This essay explores different rationales for this asymmetry. A political rationale claims that the disenfranchisement of juveniles compromises the state’s democratic authority to punish juveniles in the same way it is permitted to punish adults. A developmental rationale (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  20. Handout #6: Normative authority and Nagelian rationalism.David O. Brink - unknown
    Thomas Nagel's The Possibility of Altruism (1970) is one of the few sustained attempts to reject instrumental and prudential conceptions of practical reason and to defend the possibility of practical reason that is impartial or altruistic. Nagel makes claims about both moral motivation and practical reason, and each claim has both negative and positive constituents.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  38
    Ethics, Persuasion and Truth.David O. Brink & J. J. C. Smart - 1987 - Philosophical Review 96 (2):290.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  22.  8
    Die Kirchensoziologie in den USA und der mögliche Ertrag ihrer Arbeit für die Kirchen in Deutschland.David O. Moberg - 1965 - Zeitschrift Für Evangelische Ethik 9 (1):338-351.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23. Objectivity and dialectical methods in ethics.David O. Brink - 1999 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 42 (2):195 – 212.
    A cognitivist interpretation of moral inquiry treats it, like other kinds of inquiry, as aiming at true belief. A dialectical conception of moral inquiry represents the justification for a given moral belief as consisting in its intellectual fit with other beliefs, both moral and nonmoral. The essay appeals to semantic considerations to defend cognitivism as a default metaethical view; it defends a dialectical conception of moral inquiry by examining Sidgwick's ambivalence about the probative value of appeal to common moral beliefs (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  24. The mental logic theory of conditional propositions.David O'Brien & Manfrinati & Andrea - 2010 - In Mike Oaksford & Nick Chater (eds.), Cognition and Conditionals: Probability and Logic in Human Thought. Oxford University Press.
  25.  24
    Perfect Freedom: T. H. Green's Kantian Conception.David O. Brink - 2024 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 62 (2):289-315.
    This essay explores different conceptions of freedom in Kant, Green, and their critics. Kant introduces three kinds of freedom—negative freedom, positive freedom or autonomy, and transcendental freedom. Sidgwick objects that Kant's conception of positive freedom is unable to explain how someone might be free and responsible for the wrong choices. Though Green rejects transcendental freedom, he thinks Kant's conception of practical freedom can be defended by identifying it with the capacity to be determined by practical reason. Green identifies his own (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  10
    Between Kant and Trendelenburg: On the Genealogy of Kudryavtsev-Platonov’s Theory of Cognition.David O. Rozhin - 2023 - Kantian Journal 42 (4):35-68.
    Viktor D. Kudryavtsev-Platonov is one of the most prominent representatives of Russian religious-academic philosophy of the second half of the nineteenth century whose theory of cognition bears an imprint of the Kantian theoretical philosophy. Kudryavtsev was not only thoroughly familiar with the Königsberg thinker’s work, but offered a critically reinterpreted version of Kant’s teaching on space, time and categories of understanding. But was the Russian philosopher original in his reading and critique of Kant? In his later works Kudryavtsev often cites (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  27. The Lindley Lecture.David O. Brink - 2013 - University of Kansas.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28. Normative Perfectionism and the Kantian Tradition.David O. Brink - 2019 - Philosophers' Imprint 19.
    Perfectionism is an underexplored tradition, perhaps because of doubts about the grounds, content, and implications of perfectionist ideals. Aristotle, J.S. Mill, and T.H. Green are normative perfectionists, grounding perfectionist ideals in a normative conception of human nature involving personality or agency. This essay explores the prospects of normative perfectionism by examining Kant’s criticisms of the perfectionist tradition. First, Kant claims that the perfectionist can generate only hypothetical, not categorical, imperatives. But insofar as the normative perfectionist appeals to the normative category (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  29. Handout #7: Normative authority and Korsgaardian rationalism.David O. Brink - unknown
    In The Sources of Normativity (1996) Christine Korsgaard provides a dialectical examination of different conceptions of the sources of normativity or reasons -- conceptions that appeal to voluntarism, realism, and reflective endorsement -- that culminates in her own Kantian or neo- Kantian conception of normativity that is grounded in autonomy. Her method is dialectical (Dialectical) inasmuch as her neo-Kantian conception is supposed to reveal the truth or grain of truth in each of the three prior conceptions. Korsgaard begins Lecture 1 (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  36
    Fair Opportunity and Responsibility.David O. Brink - 2021 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Brink analyzes responsibility and its relations to desert, culpability, excuse, blame, and punishment. He argues that an agent is responsible for misconduct if and only if it is not excused, and that responsibility consists in agents having suitable cognitive and volitional capacities, and a fair opportunity to exercise these capacities.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  31.  77
    The Nature and Significance of Culpability.David O. Brink - 2019 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 13 (2):347-373.
    Culpability is not a unitary concept within the criminal law, and it is important to distinguish different culpability concepts and the work they do. Narrow culpability is an ingredient in wrongdoing itself, describing the agent’s elemental mens rea. Broad culpability is the responsibility condition that makes wrongdoing blameworthy and without which wrongdoing is excused. Inclusive culpability is the combination of wrongdoing and responsibility or broad culpability that functions as the retributivist desert basis for punishment. Each of these kinds of culpability (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  32. Moral realism and the sceptical arguments from disagreement and queerness.David O. Brink - 1984 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 62 (2):111 – 125.
  33.  49
    (1 other version)Reflecting on corporate scandals: The failure of ethical leadership.David Knights & Majella O'Leary - 2005 - Business Ethics, the Environment and Responsibility 14 (4):359–366.
  34. Ancient Wisdom and Modern Love.O'Connor David - 1993 - Brenzel.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35. Common Sense and First Principles in Sidgwick's Methods.David O. Brink - 1994 - Social Philosophy and Policy 11 (1):179-201.
    What role, if any, should our moral intuitions play in moral epistemology? We make, or are prepared to make, moral judgments about a variety of actual and hypothetical situations. Some of these moral judgments are more informed, reflective, and stable than others (call these ourconsideredmoral judgments); some we make more confidently than others; and some, though not all, are judgments about which there is substantial consensus. What bearing do our moral judgments have on philosophical ethics and the search for first (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  36. Moral motivation.David O. Brink - 1997 - Ethics 108 (1):4-32.
  37. Rawlsian Constructivism In Moral Theory.David O. Brink - 1987 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 17 (1):71-90.
    Since his article, ‘Outline for a Decision Procedure in Ethics,’ John Rawls has advocated a coherentist moral epistemology according to which moral and political theories are justified on the basis of their coherence with our other beliefs, both moral and nonmoral. A moral theory which is maximally coherent with our other beliefs is in a state which Rawls calls ‘reflective equilibrium’. In A Theory of Justice Rawls advanced two principles of justice and claimed that they are in reflective equilibrium. He (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  38.  6
    Prolegomena to Ethics.David O. Brink (ed.) - 2003 - Clarendon Press.
    A scholarly edition of a work by T.H. Green. The edition presents an authoritative text, together with an introduction, commentary notes, and scholarly apparatus.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39. Legal theory, legal interpretation, and judicial review.David O. Brink - 1988 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 17 (2):105-148.
    I argue that disputes within constitutional theory about whether recent supreme court decisions exceed the scope of legitimate judicial review and disputes within legal theory about the nature and determinacy of law are best seen and assessed as disputes over the nature of legal interpretation. I criticize the interpretive assumptions on which these disputes generally depend and defend a theory of interpretation which tends to vindicate the determinacy of law even in hard cases and the style of recent court decisions (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  40. Handout #8: Normative authority and metaphysical egoism.David O. Brink - unknown
    Doubts about the adequacy of appeals to impartial practical reason give those with rationalist sympathies reason to explore the metaphysical, and not merely strategic, reconciliation of prudence and altruism contained in metaphysical egoism. Even if we recognize impartial practical reason, the supremacy of moral demands may depend upon the plausibility of metaphysical egoism. For as long as we recognize the demands of prudence, the conflict between altruism and prudence will threaten altruism's supremacy. We might consider one version of metaphysical egoism (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  74
    Local attitudes, moral obligation, customary obedience and other cultural practices: Their influence on the process of gaining informed consent for surgery in a tertiary institution in a developing country.David O. Irabor & Peter Omonzejele - 2007 - Developing World Bioethics 9 (1):34-42.
    The process of obtaining informed consent in a teaching hospital in a developing country (e.g. Nigeria) is shaped by factors which, to the Western world, may be seen to be anti-autonomomous: autonomy being one of the pillars of an ideal informed consent. However, the mix of cultural bioethics and local moral obligation in the face of communal tradition ensures a mutually acceptable informed consent process. Paternalism is indeed encouraged by the patients who prefer to see the doctor as all-powerful and (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  42.  49
    The Rational Foundations of Ethics.David O. Brink - 1991 - Philosophical Review 100 (4):675.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  43. Situationism, responsibility, and fair opportunity.David O. Brink - 2013 - Social Philosophy and Policy 30 (1-2):121-149.
    The situationist literature in psychology claims that conduct is not determined by character and reflects the operation of the agent's situation or environment. For instance, due to situational factors, compassionate behavior is much less common than we might have expected from people we believe to be compassionate. This article focuses on whether situationism should revise our beliefs about moral responsibility. It assesses the implications of situationism against the backdrop of a conception of responsibility that is grounded in norms about the (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  44.  6
    Ancient Logs and Old Saws.David O. Ross - 1979 - American Journal of Philology 100 (2):241.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  7
    Uriosque Apertos: a Catullan Gloss.David O. Ross - 1973 - Mnemosyne 26 (1):60-62.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46. Externalist moral realism.David O. Brink - 1986 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 24 (S1):23-41.
    SOME THINK THAT MORAL REALISTS CANNOT RECOGNIZE THE PRACTICAL OR ACTION-GUIDING CHARACTER OF MORALITY AND SO REJECT MORAL REALISM. THIS FORM OF ANTI-REALISM DEPENDS UPON AN INTERNALIST MORAL PSYCHOLOGY. BUT AN EXTERNALIST MORAL PSYCHOLOGY IS MORE PLAUSIBLE AND ALLOWS THE REALIST A SENSIBLE EXPLANATION OF THE ACTION-GUIDING CHARACTER OF MORALITY. CONSIDERATION OF THE PRACTICAL CHARACTER OF MORALITY, THEREFORE, DOES NOT UNDERMINE AND, INDEED, SUPPORTS MORAL REALISM.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   81 citations  
  47. Mill's deliberative utilitarianism.David O. Brink - 1992 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 21 (1):67-103.
  48. Utilitarian Morality and the Personal Point of View.David O. Brink - 1986 - Journal of Philosophy 83 (8):417.
    Consideration of the objection from the personal point of view reveals the resources of utilitarianism. The utilitarian can offer a partial rebuttal by distinguishing between criteria of rightness and decision procedures and claiming that, because his theory is a criterion of rightness and not a decision procedure, he can justify agents' differential concern for their own welfare and the welfare of those close to them. The flexibility in utilitarianism's theory of value allows further rebuttal of this objection; objective versions of (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  49.  32
    Effects of the rate and regularity of background events on sustained attention.David O. Richter, Roderick J. Senter & Joel S. Warm - 1981 - Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society 18 (4):207-210.
  50. Prospects for Temporal Neutrality.David O. Brink - 2011 - In Craig Callender (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Time. Oxford University Press.
1 — 50 / 955